Etiquette



DP Etiquette

First rule: Don't be a jackass.

Other rules: Do not attack or insult people you disagree with. Engage with facts, logic and beliefs. Out of respect for others, please provide some sources for the facts and truths you rely on if you are asked for that. If emotion is getting out of hand, get it back in hand. To limit dehumanizing people, don't call people or whole groups of people disrespectful names, e.g., stupid, dumb or liar. Insulting people is counterproductive to rational discussion. Insult makes people angry and defensive. All points of view are welcome, right, center, left and elsewhere. Just disagree, but don't be belligerent or reject inconvenient facts, truths or defensible reasoning.

Saturday, August 10, 2019

Pragmatic Rationalism: an Anti-Ideology Ideology

Source: Vox, with info sources cited therein

Anocracies are loosely defined as part democracy and part dictatorship, or as a regime that mixes democratic with autocratic features

CONTEXT: From time to time, I try to explain my human biology-based ideology. What led to that mindset was a number of things. One was an increasing awareness of how corrupt, inept and self-serving the two-party system is. Another was the rise of deep public discontent with and distrust in American political institutions, politics, politicians and real and fake experts. Another was a possibly not completely correct understanding that all forms of government, capitalism, socialism, communism, fascism, dictatorship, theocracy, almost all of which were kleptocratic, and whatever else humans have ever tried usually led to bad to awful outcomes for most average people, or, in view of endless wars, poverty, tyranny and human misery, at least that’s how it seemed.[1] Also in the mix was the fact that human technology and activity could easily lead to destruction of civilization and maybe even species self-annihilation. If civilization collapses, billions will die.



Finally, there was a decline in respect for truth, facts and defensible, reasonable logic, something that was surprisingly motivating in looking for an appealing alternative political mindset. The disrespect had been growing for decades, but now with the rise of Trump-style populism, it is full-blown, powerful and highly corrosive to civil society.

Obviously, all of that is personal opinion and some or much of it could be at odds with objective truth. Different people will see the situation differently. The data shown in the charts suggest that things have been getting better despite all the discontent, distrust, complaining and finger pointing. Maybe too many people’s expectations, e.g., me, are out of line with what the human species can do. Maybe they’re not.

Setting that good news stuff aside, what seemed to be universal failure of all tested political ideologies, forms of government and economic systems, it was to be reasonable to look elsewhere for potential answers. It took only a brief exposure, ~30 minutes, to a book on the biology of politics, George Lakoff’s 1996 book Moral Politics: What Conservatives Know That Liberals Don't, to switch the light bulb on. It’s all about the biology, stupid -- ideology, religion and systems of government are beside the point. People are going to be people. Period. That lesson came fast and easy. What came after was slow and hard.

THE IDEOLOGY: The science is in and the debate is over: If serving the public interest or common good is the goal, politics is more incoherent and irrational than needed. Arguably, it is more incoherent and irrational than not.[2]

Bad leaders usually share a few traits that are deeply ingrained in human biology. They (i) disrespect or completely ignore truth and facts, (ii) don't care if they apply completely bogus logic or reason to whatever truth and facts they are claiming, and (iii) cite their facts, logic, ideology and morals as the basis for the best outcomes for the people, but (iv) usually (> 95% of the time ?) generate results that greatly benefit them, their family, friends, supporters and/or ideology, while doing little or nothing for, or actually harming, the public interest. Sooner or later, it always seems to turn out about like that. The last century may have some contrary lessons, but listening to everyone complain today, one wouldn't think that.

If one accepts the fact (not opinion) that human biology is by far the dominant force in politics and the opinion that the public interest usually gets the shaft while elites frolic in semi-utopia, then what can one do for politics? Over time, this ideology slowly came into focus:

Ignore political ideologies to the extent possible and to the extent possible hold as the highest moral political values (i) fidelity to objective truth, (ii) fidelity to reason that is as unbiased or logically defensible as possible, and (iii) use that to inform and shape policy and laws in service to the public interest based on a competition of ideas.

The public interest is a complicated, contested concept. It will probably be debated forever. However, putting that aside, one definition of service to the public interest can be described like this: It means governance based on identifying a rational, optimum balance between serving public, individual and commercial interests based on an objective, fact- and logic-based analysis of competing policy choices, while (1) being reasonably transparent and responsive to public opinion, (2) protecting and growing the American economy, (3) fostering individual economic and personal growth opportunity, (4) defending personal freedoms and the American standard of living, (5) protecting national security and the environment, (6) increasing transparency, competition and efficiency in commerce when possible, and (7) fostering global peace, stability and prosperity whenever reasonably possible, all of which is constrained by (i) honest, reality-based fiscal sustainability that limits the scope and size of government and regulation to no more than what is needed and (ii) genuine respect for the U.S. constitution and the rule of law with a particular concern for limiting unwarranted legal complexity and ambiguity to limit opportunities to subvert the constitution and the law.

Obviously, some of that will be instantly criticized, e.g., protecting and growing the American economy is unsustainable and completely at odds with protecting the environment. That's right, there are internal contradictions and the way that conception of service to the public interest deals with conflicting goals is to focus on “identifying a rational, optimum balance” among competing interests.

The point is to build a mindset that relentlessly looks for merit and tangible results for the public interest. Weak argument such as, “What’s good for GM is good for America” isn't persuasive. What’s good for the public interest is good for America. Notice the mindset change from the specific to the broad.

The point of the ideology is to make it a little harder to do politics based on opacity, lies and fake logic. Opacity, lies and fake logic are invariably used by special interests, bad leaders, e.g., Donald Trump, and ideologues to win arguments. The point is to make politics perform the best it can within the limits of human biology.

Will it work? Not at present. Maybe never. At the moment, American politics is turning toward more lies, fake logic and opacity, not less. Maybe this read is wrong, but the American public has lost patience and is succumbing to fear and other reason-killing emotions. There is some evidence that at least some humans can be noticeably more rational about politics. But whether that mindset can ever gain mainstream acceptance is an open question. In view of human history and biology, it seems highly unlikely.



Footnotes:
1. There is data showing that for many poor people in the US and probably most other countries, the last 100 years or so have been the best time in human history to be poor in terms of access to basic necessities such as food, public education, clean water, sanitation and health care. If that data is basically correct, things could be a whole lot worse than they are now.

2. This is how some scientists see politics: “. . . . the typical citizen drops down to a lower level of mental performance as soon as he enters the political field. He argues and analyzes in a way which he would readily recognize as infantile within the sphere of his real interests. . . . cherished ideas and judgments we bring to politics are stereotypes and simplifications with little room for adjustment as the facts change. . . . . the real environment is altogether too big, too complex, and too fleeting for direct acquaintance. We are not equipped to deal with so much subtlety, so much variety, so many permutations and combinations. Although we have to act in that environment, we have to reconstruct it on a simpler model before we can manage it.”



B&B orig: 5/29/18

Antecedents to Pragmatic Politics: Karl Popper

Popper commenting on confirmation bias in politics and life generally

In one recent essay in a series on the origins of modern liberalism, The Exiles Fight Back, the Economist describes the reaction of three Viennese intellectuals in responding to the tyranny and terror that both centralized power, e.g., fascism, and collectivism, e.g., socialism, lead to in the years leading up to and after World War 2. The three, Frederich Hayek, Joseph Schumpeter and Karl Popper, were reacting to extremist political ideologies and, in their own ways, criticizing the dangers of centralized power: “Each was troubled by the Anglo-Saxon countries’ complacency that totalitarianism could never happen to them. Yet warning signs abounded. The Depression in the 1930s had made government intervention seem desirable to most economists. Now the Soviet Union was a wartime ally, and criticism of its terror-based regime was frowned upon. Perhaps most worryingly, in Britain and America war had brought centralised authority and a single collective purpose: victory. Who could be sure that this command-and-control machine would be switched off?”

According to the Economist essay, the three men did not cooperate, but instead a division of thinking arose spontaneously: “Popper sought to blow up the intellectual foundations of totalitarianism and explain how to think freely. Hayek set out to demonstrate that, to be safe, economic and political power must be diffuse. Schumpeter provided a new metaphor for describing the energy of a market economy: creative destruction.”

Popper’s war effort: Popper's 1945 book, The Open Society and Its Enemies, begins with an attack on historicism, which the Economist describes as “grand theories dressed up as laws of history, which make sweeping prophecies about the world and sideline individual volition.” That may be a definition that at least some people would dispute.

The Economist comments on Popper’s thinking: “Hegel’s metaphysics and his insistence that the state has its own spirit are dismissed as ‘mystifying cant’. Popper gives a sympathetic hearing to Marx’s critique of capitalism, but views his predictions as little better than a tribal religion.

In 1934 Popper had written about the scientific method, in which hypotheses are advanced and scientists seek to falsify them. Any hypothesis left standing is a kind of knowledge. This conditional, modest concept of truth recurs in ‘The Open Society’. ‘We must break with the habit of deference to great men,’ Popper argues. A healthy society means a competition for ideas, not central direction, and critical thinking that considers the facts, not who is presenting them. Contrary to Marx’s claim, democratic politics was not a pointless charade. But Popper thought that change was only possible through experimentation and piecemeal policy, not utopian dreams and large-scale schemes executed by an omniscient elite.

Taken together, in the 1940s Hayek, Popper and Schumpeter offered a muscular attack on collectivism, totalitarianism and historicism, and a restatement of the virtues of liberal democracy and markets. Capitalism is not an engine for warmongering exploitation (as Marxists believed), nor a static oligarchy, nor a high road to crisis. Accompanied by the rule of law and democracy, it is the best way for individuals to retain their liberty.

The collapse of the Soviet Union in the 1990s vindicated Popper’s searing attack on the stupidity of grand historical schemes.”

Since this is about political theory, criticisms are to be expected: “The three Austrians are vulnerable to common criticisms. The concentration of their intellectual firepower on left-wing ideologies (rather than Nazism) can seem lopsided. Schumpeter had been complacent about the rise of Nazism; but for Popper and Hayek, the devastation unleashed by fascism was self-evident. Both argued that Marxism and fascism had common roots: the belief in a collective destiny; the conviction that the economy should be marshalled to a common goal and that a self-selected elite should give the orders.

Another criticism is that they put too little emphasis on taming the savagery of the market, particularly given the misery of unemployment in the 1930s.”

In addition to political and philosophical criticisms, advancing science arguably has brought some of the logic basis for Popper’s thinking into question. For example, one analyst argued that Popper’s thinking rested on assumptions such as (1) no precise predictions are possible in the social sciences, and (2) no short term predictions are possible in the social sciences. Depending on how one defines a ‘precise’ or ‘short term’ prediction in the social sciences, Popper appears to be wrong about both of those beliefs. Both kinds of predictions are have been documented.

Also different is new technology, which appears to be undermining Popper’s 1940s point of view that knowledge was contingent and dispersed: “A free, decentralised society allocated resources better than planners, who could only guess at the knowledge dispersed among millions of individuals. Today, by contrast, the most efficient system may be a centralised one. Big data could allow tech firms and governments to “see” the entire economy and co-ordinate it far more efficiently than Soviet bureaucrats ever could.

Schumpeter thought monopolies were temporary castles that were blown away by new competitors. Today’s digital elites seem entrenched. Popper and Hayek might be fighting for a decentralisation of the internet, so that individuals owned their own data and identities. Unless power is dispersed, they would have pointed out, it is always dangerous.”

If digital elites are entrenched and fairly resistant to creative destruction, then it would seem that regulation is one way to deal with the danger inherent in accumulated power. Today, some see giants such as Google, Facebook, Twitter and Microsoft as being in, or having made, a transition from benign to malicious. Part of the logic is simple. There is so damn much money to be made. One problem with jumps right out: To some extent, all that damn money has bought government so intelligent regulation is off the table. The other problem, which exacerbates the first, is sweeping anti-government, pro-business political ideology that currently dominates American politics. Together, the two problems are positively toxic. An intelligent balance cannot be struck.

Popper & Pragmatism: The Economist comments: “Popper was deeply concerned about workers’ conditions; in ‘The Open Society’ he lists approvingly the labour regulations put in place since Marx wrote about children toiling in factories. He thought pragmatic policies could gradually improve the lot of all.” That accords with Popper’s belief in experimentation and piecemeal policy.[1] That mindset is also compatible with the brand of politics advocated here, a pragmatic, biology-based, anti-bias ideology.

Footnote:
1. In his 1998 book (pages 394-395), The User Illusion, Tor Norretrander argues that information theory (the complexity of social forces) shows that free markets are a more efficient way forward to social progress than planned economies. The argument is that free markets are more efficient at allowing successes to succeed and failures to fail: “The collapse of communism is a manifestation of the low bandwidth of the social domain, the low capacity of language compared to the actual wealth of information in our needs. Feedback from society to planners cannot take place efficiently enough over the conscious linguistic bandwidth. Supply and demand are better at returning this information. This is ironic, for the whole idea of socialism is that barter and the market economy discard too much information.”

Norretranders may or may not be right about what the ‘whole idea of socialism’ is. Nonetheless, his point about information content in social reactions to offers of various goods and service in the economy compared to what elites and central planners would provide seems self-evident on the basis of unbiased common sense (logic). That argument seems about as powerful as any that a planned economy will not be as efficient in the long run as a free market economy. As always, the trick is for free market economies is how to regulate to balance unfettered capitalism’s tendency toward corruption, brutality and misery without crippling it. Unfortunately, balancing is not generally compatible with political, economic, religious or philosophical ideologies that do not look to trial and error pragmatism as a core value.

B&B orig: 8/31/18

Friday, August 9, 2019

Chapter Review: Plato, Aristotle and the Origins of Political Psychology

Plato

In his 2103 book, Political Psychology: Neuroscience, Genetics and Politics, political science professor George Marcus describes the origin of the Western intellectual framework that shapes and constrains how social sciences approach the science of politics. That framework both reveals and hides questions for research. For the most part, Marcus conveys a cautionary tale about the modern mindset and its conceptions of time, reason and emotion.

He is trying to teach self-awareness and some humility in the face of the subtle power of the modern intellectual framework. It is a lens or mindset that can distort reality and understanding. Nonetheless, we view politics through that modern Western lens even though it sometimes misleads us. The trick for the open-minded is to be self-aware and on guard. The following is based on chapter 3, A Short History of a Long Tradition.

The short history and its lessons were written for students of political psychology and related disciplines such as sociology. However, the core facts and ideas are helpful, maybe necessary, for people who want to be informed, rational citizens operating on the basis of objective evidence to the extent that influencer is available to the public. Even though social sciences knowledge and reality is constrained by empirical data and error-correction by peer-review, there is a powerful, subtle agenda that operates mostly unconsciously.

The Enlightenment Agenda: That modern agenda is grounded in the 17th and 18th century intellectual ferment in the Europe and the US. The ferment is called The Enlightenment and it constitutes a powerful social science agenda. Marcus points out that an agenda identifies ideas that are seen as important and what one would expect to find based on those ideas or assumptions. Regarding The Enlightenment, he comments: “Those ideas, and the agenda that they defined, have become so widely shared and so deeply embedded that they have become largely invisible with few to challenge its assumptions. And, as Plato argued, shared beliefs are not only likely to become invisible, when a rare iconoclast raises a challenge to accepted wisdoms, the response is hardly a welcome one.” Plato in his classic work, The Republic, in defense of philosopher kings and enlightened aristocrats as the best form of government, writes that the iconoclast will be killed. That is definitely not a welcome response.

Marcus points out that the human mind both hides and protects the unity we think we see. That Enlightenment unity gives the world coherence and meaning, even in situations where there is no rational basis for coherence. Regarding how the mind operates and self-deceives, Marcus comments: “As we shall see, Plato anticipated this research by more than two millennia. . . . . Rather, we all evince this same protective shield. The goal of the sections that follow is to make the invisible visible. This chapter is intended to ruffle some feathers: yours in particular.” One can only wonder what it is like to take professor Marcus’ political psychology class.

Also, one can only wonder how it was that Plato, by simple observation alone in his lifetime (c.428-347 B.C.), observed and correctly interpreted the fundamentally self-deceiving basis by which the mind operates when dealing with politics. That must have been some mind.

Aristotle

Two Western Conceptions of Time: Pre-Enlightenment & Enlightenment: Professor Marcus’ short history described two different Western conceptions of time. He argues that understanding the two different conceptions of time are necessary to understanding politics. Existing evidence shows that most people are inconsistent about which conception of time they apply in their thinking, and instead “most of us adhere haphazardly to one or the other as circumstances warrant.” The pre-Enlightenment mind conceived of time as operating in cycles. In that mindset, political regimes started, grew, matured and then lost vitality and withered. It was an endless cycle. The parallels to spring, summer, fall and winter are obvious. The modern or Enlightenment conception of time see it as a one-way arrow, always moving forward with increasing knowledge and social progress.

The philosopher Hannah Arendt is credited with pointing out that the distinction between the premodern and the modern conceptions of time constituted a radical mindset change. In the premodern mind, political regime change was seen as a ‘revolution’, which reflected the view of time as cyclical. Both mindsets have major implications for how the world is perceived and understood. In the case of the premodern mindset: “We search for the recurring patterns that provide us with confidence that our past foretells our future.” In other words, the cycle of time defines our fate. In turn, that leads many people to a belief that it is best not to go against our fate or destiny because that can lead to disaster. At this point, Marcus argues: “Time as cyclical, especially when married to the idea of fate and destiny, is inherently conservative, protective of the established social order, established political authority, and dominant traditions.” That thought leads to this important point:

“In addition, with time as cyclical, the debate between advocates of democracy, such as Aristotle, and those who advocated aristocratic rule, such as Plato, is stable. Nothing new will alter that debate as human nature is fixed and our natures either suit us for democracy, as some have it, or for aristocracy as others have it.”

Marcus then points out that with the premodern view of time as cyclic, the role of political psychology is limited because what government and politics can do, at most, is ease the passage of time for people. Trying to challenge the limits that cyclical time imposes is pointless folly. From that point of view, an important political psychology goal would be to develop knowledge of what leads to virtue and what leads to corruption. Obviously, that is an important goal for adherents of the modern linear, or probably any other, view of time. At least, that is how it appears to this observer.

By contrast with the premodern continual vision of self-renewing cycles of time, the modern or Enlightenment thinkers “reconceived time as an engine that, as a train on tracks, drives along a line from past to future. Time as progress replaced time as cyclical repetition. . . . . The modern conception of time understands time as a linear progression from an older and archaic way of life to a new, younger, and more progressive way of life.” Here, life is seen to progress from early, immature stages of political belief and behavior to later, more refined stages. The later stages are better able to adapt to changing forces such as social, economic and environmental changes.

For example, Karl Marx saw politics as an inevitable progression of class conflict from feudalism to mercantilism to capitalism, to socialism and finally to communism. In a way, time is seen as an arrow. For Marx, the engine of progress is class struggle. For Immanuel Kant, the engine is war. For Alexis de Tocqueville, based on his direct observations of, and thinking about, the new US democracy in 1831 and thereafter, the engine of progress is democracy: “Hence, democracy becomes the institutional regime most likely to accelerate progress because a democratic regime enables more people to engage in private and public deliberation on the means by which their sundry preferences can be justified and realized.”

Pre-Modern vs Modern Visions of the Role of Emotion and Reason: Disagreements on the nature and political importance of emotion and reason date at least back to Plato and Aristotle. Plato’s view led him to the conclusion that the masses are too influenced by emotion and thus enlightened and trained aristocrats and/or an enlightened philosopher king constituted the best form of government. Plato argued that knowledge alone should be the basis for governance, and as mentioned above, people will kill in defense of the false beliefs, myths and illusions that most people live by. He saw that as placing beliefs over truth: “Plato argued that to give the public a role in public affairs would introduce assertive opinion, what today political psychologists would call ‘motivated reasoning’. Hence, it is no surprise that Plato predicted that when truth confronts belief, the result would be the killing of truth-sayers.”

By contrast, Aristotle advocated for democracy based on the collective wisdom of the crowd as a source of intellectual and situational diversity. Aristotle believed rule by many was a better basis for governance than intellectual and situational diversity of one or a few rulers. In his view, collective public wisdom was superior to the wisdom of the one or the few. He saw governance as best based on a combination of objective knowledge and subjective goals of the people. Aristotle correctly understood that emotions and passions cannot be ignored in political thinking.

Marcus points out that Plato’s teacher, Socrates, was put to death by a democratically elected Athenian jury precisely for the crime of challenging sacred Athenian beliefs. Could that have influenced Plato to some extent? It is also interesting to note that Aristotle was an Athenian where political leaders were elected. Plato was citizen of Sparta, which was governed by kings.

Marcus commented on reason and emotion: “The interest in reason and emotion arose because it addressed the foremost question that has long engaged us: Where can we find the knowledge so that whichever regime we adopt it will be virtuous?” That arguably is the central question of our time. For example, why is the obvious corruption of President Trump seemingly acceptable to so many of his supporters and populists in general?

Emotion was generally viewed by all observers as an impediment to rational, good government and thus something that people should and can set aside. Modern cognitive science and neuroscience has shown it is impossible to separate emotion from politics. Emotion is biologically unavoidable. And, it can be very helpful. What needs to be kept in mind is that emotion can mislead and sow deep civil divisions, misery and war. When that happens, self-awareness is necessary for conscious reason to temper irrational, destructive emotions. Marcus argued that emotions are not rational.

The Three Key Influencers: Reason, Emotion & Interest: In view of the possibility, if not inevitability, of emotion in politics, philosophers have long struggled with how to deal with that reality. Enlightenment thinkers came up with the concept of interest, meaning self-interest and the public interest, to account for differences between conscious reason and emotion, which exerts effects in mostly unconscious ways. Pre-Enlightenment thinking held that reason and emotion were the main influencers. Enlightenment thinking held that reason, emotion and interest were the driving influencers. Current research has shown that interest is a powerful unconscious influence on perceptions of political reality and thinking or reasoning about it.

Therein lies a major issue: “Because interests do not reside in the self-aware mental region, we may not know what our ‘interests’ are.” That can lead to false beliefs about what objectively a person’s or the public’s interests are. The power of interest arises from a combination of unconscious calculating emotion and conscious reason heavily influenced by the emotion. The evidence that interest exerts major influences on both perception and reason is solid and not debated among experts. Evidence that people are significantly unaware of their own and the public interests is strong, maybe close to the point of being settled science.

Conservatism vs Liberalism: Marcus points out that most social scientists self-identify as liberals. One study found more than 95% of social scientists are liberals.[1] Therein lies a problem for the social sciences. Shared liberal values become invisible. That can obscure the conservative point of view and its values. Marcus cautions: “Perhaps the answer is that in any given case, our species is better off for having both orientations distributed among us than having just one modal position.” He argues that there are potential dangers and rewards in taking either a liberal or a conservative path. He also criticizes the Enlightenment view that has unduly downplayed emotions, thereby skewing visions of reality. He sees progress as both an empirical tale and a moral story.

The Human Condition: Marcus gives a sobering assessment. Progress has not been a straight line. Politics has not gone according to the Enlightenment plan. Accumulating evidence continues to show that reason and rationality is not displacing the role of emotion. Interest helps explain some aspects, but emotion continues to be a powerful influencer. The issue is coming to terms with what it is to be human. In reference to economics, sociology and social psychology there is an ongoing problem: “Blindness to the constraints induced by progressive convictions is not limited to political psychology. . . . . The problem of explanation without a clear recognition and understanding of the normative foundations of political psychology [] will limit the value of our research to show us what is and what is not plausible, let alone possible.”

Clearly, the evidence-based anti-bias ideology advocated here at B&B crashes directly into this concern about the nature and limits of the human mind acting alone and in groups, tribes and societies. How much more and what more, if anything, are possible in terms of evidence- and reason-based politics? The answers are unknowable. So far, no major ideology and social institution predicated on elevating the role reason to some non-trivial extent has had a fair test on a large, nation-size scale. Given that, the immense power of social institutions as sociologist Peter Berger described in his 1963 book, Invitation to Sociology, has never been tested in human history.

The situation is not all bleak. Marcus point out that neuroscience is rapidly changing our view of time, reason, emotion and knowledge, all of which can point to new possibilities. Therein lies the best hope for new understandings in how to try to deal with the problems that political psychology has been struggling with at least since Plato and Aristotle engaged in their sparring match over two thousand years ago.

Footnote:
1. One observer pointed out that maybe conservatives avoid the social sciences because much of what has been found contradicts conservatism to some extent. Some research suggests that conservatives are generally more uncomfortable with cognitive dissonance associated with ambiguity and contradictions than most liberals tend to be. In other words, social science just might be too psychologically uncomfortable for most conservative minds to find much appeal in that branch of the sciences.

B&B orig: 11/22/18

Chapter Review: Time, Memory & Unconsciousness



CONTEXT: A defensible belief holds that existing political ideologies are more bad than good for various reasons related to cognitive biology and social behavior and influences. That is what B&B argues. Ideologies tend to foster in-group thinking and behaviors and that tends to make it easy to distort reality, facts, truths and thinking into beliefs that are unreasonably detached from reality, facts and truths. It makes politics more irrational than it has to be. One idea would propose that people simply adopt a science mindset that looks to impose more rationality into politics.

In his blog post at Neurologica entitled, Against Ideology, skeptic Steven Novella discusses some thinking about problems with existing political ideologies. Novella comments on problems with ideology and the exhilarating experience of walking away from one: “The skeptical movement has always struggled with some unavoidable ironies. We are like a group for people who don’t like to join groups. We actively tell our audience not to trust us (don’t trust any single source – verify with logic and evidence). Our belief is that you really should not have beliefs, only tentative conclusions. Essentially, our ideology is anti-ideology.

This approach is both empowering and freeing. One of the most common observations I hear from those who, after consuming skeptical media for a time, abandon some prior belief system or ideology, is that they feel as if a huge weight has been lifted from their shoulders. They feel free from the oppressive burden of having to support one side or ideology, even against evidence and reason. Now they are free to think whatever they want, whatever is supported by the evidence. They don’t have to carry water for their ‘team.’

At the same time, this is one of the greatest challenges for skeptical thinking, because it seems to run upstream against a strong current of human nature. We are tribal, we pick a side and defend it, especially if it gets wrapped up in our identity or world-view.”

That, in a nutshell, is one of the biggest problems with standard ideologies, all of which are fairly called ‘pro-bias’ ideologies. Existing ideologies are powerful motivators to distort reality, facts, truths, and reason whenever those any of those things contradict or undercut the chosen ideology. Distortion and ensuing irrationality is probably the norm, not the exception.

------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

The Anti-Bias Ideology: A Simplified Explanation: Some years ago, it made sense to reject ideology as a framework for doing and thinking about politics. The science mindset of pragmatic, evidence-driven trial, error and course corrections seemed to be the best approach. Then, after some years of looking into cognitive biology and social behavior, it seemed that one cannot eliminate emotion and morals from the process. That lead to a science- and morals-based 'anti-bias' political ideology that focuses on the the key sources of irrationality, incivility and failure. Four core moral principles seem to be the most anti-biasing. The morals are (i) fidelity to seeing less biased fact and truth, (ii) fidelity to applying less biased conscious reason, service to the public interest (defined as a transparent competition of ideas among competing interests) based on the facts and reason, and (iv) willingness to reasonably compromise according to political, economic and environmental circumstances point to.

After considering politics through human history, most or all bad leaders (tyrants, oligarchs, kleptocrats, etc.) seem to share the four key traits. They generally disregard, deny or hide facts and truths when it is politically convenient to do so, which is most of the time. Bad leaders also routinely apply biased (bogus) reasoning to facts, fake or not, typically to foment unwarranted emotional responses such as fear, anger, bigotry, racism and distrust-hate toward out-groups or ‘the enemy’. All of that irrationality is focused in service to a corrupt self-serving conception of the public interest, and it is reinforced by a corrupt, self-serving unwillingness to compromise.

If one accepts that those four bad traits of bad leaders are real and the norm, then arguably the four core moral values of a pragmatic, evidence-based anti-bias political ideology would seem to make sense if one wants to fight against the rise and ability of bad leaders to gain power and then do bad things to people and societies.

The question is, would this ‘anti-bias’ mindset or ideology work. Maybe. Maybe not. The experiment appears to not have been tried in modern times with modern means for mass communication of dark free speech (lies, deceit, unwarranted opacity, unwarranted emotional manipulation, mostly fomenting unwarranted fear, intolerance, anger, and hate, etc.). Testing an anti-bias ideology for success or failure is a multi-generational social engineering experiment. It would be great to see it tried. Even if it failed, the failure might shed enough light on the human condition and politics to reveal another more civilized, sustainable and efficient way to do politics.

Anti-bias is not just the scientific method applied to politics: The anti-bias ideology isn't just adoption of a scientific method mindset. It expressly includes moral values and treats them as such. In science, there tends to be less outright lying and grossly bogus reasoning. Those things tend to get called out and careers then tend to crash and burn if a course correction isn't made. In science, errors happen, but they are typically mistakes, not lies. Flawed reasoning in science tends to be honest support of a hypothesis, not sloppy thinking in defense of an indefensible ideological belief. In these regards, the anti-bias ideology directly accounts for human nature. Science tends to downplay that in a belief that fact and logic will quench errors to a reasonable extent. That may be generally true for science, but it is clearly not true for politics. Science and politics are simply not the same thing, at least not yet with existing pro-bias ideologies that dominate.

White-faced whistling ducks guarding the waterfall 

 B&B orig: 10/30/18

Chapter Review: A Classless Society

Hannah Arendt, 1906-1975

INTRODUCTION: In her 1951 book, The Origins of Totalitarianism, political theorist Hannah Arendt traces the historical origins of anti-Semitism, racism, imperialism and totalitarianism. Regarding Arendt, Wikipedia comments: “Arendt is widely considered one of the most important political philosophers of the twentieth century.” Arendt’s political ideology is hard to pin down, but maybe it can best be described as anti-totalitarian and pragmatic rationalist-realist. Her depiction of the human condition is cold, realist and disquieting.

Arendt, born in 1906, was an educated intellectual and a German Jew. She escaped Nazi Germany a few months before Europe closed its borders. She was thus personally familiar with the social moral hypocrisy and decay of European nations and the rising horrors the hypocrisy and decay engendered. Although anti-Semitism and racism predated the industrial revolution, Arendt argues it led to the modern foundations of anti-Semitism, racism as a political ideology, imperialism and totalitarianism.

This review was inspired by a search for where President Trump might fit among Western demagogues and tyrants from the point of view of someone who never knew Trump as a political leader. Trump was five years old when Arendt published her book. Regarding the book, Wikipedia comments: “The book is regularly listed as one of the best non-fiction books of the 20th century.”

Apparently, this reviewer's thought is not unique. Trump has inspired others to look to books on political theory for insight into whatever it is that Trump is. One reviewer wrote in 2017: “The book whose success is a surprise, however, is Hannah Arendt’s The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951). At 752 pages, Arendt’s magnum opus is not brief, and with its panoramic exploration of history, philosophy, politics and psychology, the book can exercise a reader’s mind. But recently it sold out on Amazon . . . . .”

The Origins of Totalitarianism is organized in three parts. Part one, Antisemitism chapters 1-4, Imperialism, chapters 5-9, and Totalitarianism, chapters 10-13. Given Arendt’s dense writing style and the length of the book, reviews of individual chapters are necessary to reasonably summarize the content and tenor of what Arendt is trying to convey. A review of the entire book seems inadequate, or at least beyond this reviewer’s capacity.



REVIEW: The Classless Society (chapter 10): Arendt opens chapter 10 with the observation that totalitarian regimes are transient. The conditions that lead to the possibility of a totalitarian regime are so unusual that only two existed in her time, Hitler’s Nazi Germany and Stalin’s Russia. Other contenders from the past might include Mussolini in Italy. Arendt does not put Mussolini in the totalitarian category, relegating him instead to the status of mere dictator. Totalitarians are different from dictators. Totalitarians seek global control and they ‘atomize’ their populations such that social classes, groups and even families are broken down. Atomized societies are classless societies.

Morality, truth and history are swept away as impediments to total control. Absolute, unquestioning loyalty to the leader is the only acceptable norm for the citizen. The propaganda and lies employed does not just play on “ignorance and stupidity”:
For the propaganda of totalitarian movements which precede and accompany totalitarian regimes is invariably frank as it is mendacious, and would-be totalitarian leaders usually start their careers by boasting of their past crimes and carefully outlining their future ones. The Nazis ‘were convinced that evil-doing in our time has a morbid force of attraction’. Bolshevik assurances inside and outside Russia that they do not recognize ordinary moral standards have become a mainstay of communist propaganda, and experience has proved time and again that the propaganda value of evil deeds and general contempt for moral standards is independent of mere self-interest, supposedly the most powerful psychological factor in politics. The attraction of evil and crime for the mob mentality is nothing new. . . . . .

Arendt elaborates on propaganda and the alliance between the mob and intellectual elites, who in their cynicism at the time were attracted to shiny and strange new things. In their cynicism, the elites were even willing to see the collapse of civilization “for the fun of seeing how those who had been unjustly excluded in the past forced their way into it.”
To this aversion of the intellectual elite for official historiography, to its conviction that history, which was a forgery anyway, might as well be the playground of crackpots, must be added the terrible, demoralizing fascination in the possibility that gigantic lies and monstrous falsehoods may cease to be objective and become a mere matter of power and cleverness, of pressure and infinite repetition. Not Stalin’s or Hitler’s skill in the art of lying but the fact that they were able to organize the masses into a collective unit to back up their lies with impressive magnificence, exerted the fascination.

That paints a bleak picture of significant portions of societies drowning in cynicism and willing to accept social collapse in exchange for something different, or at least entertaining. In that milieu, neither democracy nor the cold morality of a relentless quest for acquisition of greater wealth by the bourgeoisie seemed worth defending. Arendt argues that the morals, or lack thereof, of the capitalists had subverted democratic norms and put economic and property concerns before all other things. In essence, European nations had been conquered by a ruthless economic ideology and many people in society saw that, or at least felt the sting.

Arendt describes the sources of social cynicism and deep distrust she sees in the historical record.
An atmosphere in which all traditional values and propositions had evaporated (after the nineteenth century ideologies had refuted each other and exhausted their vital appeal) in a sense made it easier to accept patently absurd propositions than the old truths which had become pious banalities, precisely because nobody could be expected to take the absurdities seriously. . . . . In the growing prevalence of mob attitudes and convictions – which were actually the attitudes and convictions of the bourgeoisie cleansed of hypocrisy – those who traditionally hated the bourgeoisie and had voluntarily left respectable society saw only the lack of hypocrisy and respectability, not the content itself. Since the bourgeoisie claimed to be the guardians of Western traditions and confounded on all moral issues by parading publicly virtues which it only did not possess in private and business life, but held in contempt, it seemed revolutionary to admit cruelty, disregard of human values, and general amorality, because this at least destroyed the duplicity on which the existing society seemed to rest.

Thus, despite the bleak pictures of societies that Arendt describes, one can see in the reaction to a hypocritical and morally bankrupt bourgeoisie, many people were clearly repulsed by the corrupt sleaze at the top. That reaction is not one coming from pure apathy. That may have led to political apathy and grudging, silent tolerance of democratic governments. But at the least average people were looking for moral consistency, even if they could not see it was the morality of an insanely vicious and evil totalitarianism.

Arendt argues that totalitarians rise to power in two steps. First they rely on the mob for initial support, and then they harvest the masses and stay in power as long as the masses stay loyal to the leader. For Arendt, the mob is not the industrial working class or the people as a whole, but it is “the refuse of all classes . . . . . the riff-raff of bohemians, crackpots, gangsters and conspirators.” She asserts that although totalitarian leaders rise from the mob, the early supporters are cast aside or killed once the leader has power. What seems to attract the mob to totalitarians is their status as social castaways and the promise of social destruction with a new world order. The mob sees and rejects the deep hypocrisy of the dominant bourgeoisie morals and social norms that nation states of the time were built on. In a sense, the mob was the collateral damage of the industrial revolution, including its grotesque concentration of wealth at the very top.

Arendt’s vision of totalitarianism includes two other necessary components. One is a circumstance where the masses, normally apathetic, non-political citizens have “acquired the appetite for political organization.” This reflects a disaffected population that tolerates democratic government without enthusiasm. The totalitarian leader relies on charm, charisma and relentless propaganda to help create and shape the political appetite. These previously apathetic populations can be captured by totalitarian movements. The other component is a sufficient population of the masses. “Only where great masses are superfluous or can be spared without disastrous results of depopulation is totalitarian rule, as distinguished from a totalitarian movement, at all possible. . . . . they [German and Russian totalitarian movements] recruited their members from this mass of apparently indifferent people whom all other parties had given up as too apathetic or too stupid for their attention.” Arendt asserted that totalitarian movements in Eastern European countries all led to mere dictatorships because they did not have sufficient populations for the human slaughter necessary to atomize subject societies or nations. In all of this, Arendt casts the masses in a constantly negative light, e.g., inarticulate, apathetic or stupid.

With the necessary support of the masses, Arendt sees the end of two illusions that democratic governments deluded themselves with:
The first was that people in its majority had taken an active part in its government and that each individual was in sympathy with one’s own or somebody else’s party. On the contrary, the movements showed that the politically neutral and indifferent masses could easily be the majority in a democratically ruled country . . . . . The second illusion exploded by the totalitarian movements was that these politically indifferent masses did not matter . . . . . democratic government had rested as much on the silent approbation and tolerance of the indifferent and inarticulate sections of the people as on the articulate and visible institutions and organizations of the country.

Arendt makes many other important points. One is her assertion that, for the typical citizen, it does not make much difference what brand of totalitarianism one lives under. “Practically speaking, it will make little difference whether totalitarian movements adopt the pattern of Nazism or Bolshevism, organize the masses in the name of race or class, pretend to follow the laws of life and nature or of dialectics and economics.” In an atomized, classless society, the underlying ideology is as irrelevant as truth and reason.

Another assertion Arendt makes is that neither Nazism nor Bolshevism constituted a new form of government or that their political goals were ever attained, even after the movements attained power and control.
Their idea of domination was something that no state and no mere apparatus of violence can ever achieve, but only a movement that is constantly kept in motion; namely the permanent domination of each individual in each and every sphere of life. The seizure of power through means of violence is never an end in itself but only the means to an end, and the seizure of power in any given country is only a welcome transitory stage but never the end of the movement. . . . . a political goal that would constitute the end of the movement simply does not exist.

That seems to argue that totalitarianism, in view of its disregard for truth, morals, social class and most everything else, is simply an endless process of demanding and receiving loyalty and not much else. Whether one can count that as a form of government or an ideology seems to be open to debate.

Is Trump a would-be totalitarian, or just a would-be dictator?: Based on chapter 10, Trump does not look to be a true totalitarian. Not only are circumstances in America not ripe, with powerful institutions standing in his way, Trump himself is too shallow and self-centered to aspire to the kind of brutal rule that Hitler and Stalin conceived. Aspects of Trump fit the totalitarian mold, e.g., his constant mendacity, ability to play on people’s discontent, contempt for democratic institutions and a lack of any cognizable moral compass are all there. But Trump just does not have it in him to kill millions by playing on racism and/or class conflicts. That is the case even if the independent press and independent law enforcement and our independent judiciary were swept away, which is what Trump would very much like to see. Trump wants to be a dictator and he makes that very clear in his public statements. Nonetheless, he clearly falls short of the creatively vicious mind and the work ethic it would take. Trump likes looking at himself in the mirror far too much for that kind of a project to appeal.

That said, Trump’s authoritarian successor just might consider it. Conditions will be better. Trump has done much to plow and prepare the soil for a serious totalitarian to make a run at total power. Trump has weakened the press by fomenting baseless distrust and his party is now openly favoring single-party rule status and willing to break laws to get it. Trump and his party are packing federal courts with unqualified and/or extremist ideologues, which is an important step in destroying judicial independence. Trump’s view of the rule of law is also clear – he hates it. For Trump, the law only applies to enemies, not himself or friends.

The 2020 elections will be interesting, to say the least. Whether they turn out to be frightening is a key question.



B&B orig: 1/4/18

Chapter Review: The Political Emancipation of the Bourgeoisie



Expansion is everything. I would annex the planets if I could. – Cecil Rhodes (1853-1902), capitalist, founder of the African territory of Rhodesia (now Zimbabwe and Zambia), founder of the Rhodes scholarship, and founder of the De Beers diamond company and the De Beers global diamond monopoly, despairing of the obvious economic limits of conquering planet Earth

Antisemitism (not merely the hatred of Jews), imperialism (not merely conquest), totalitarianism (not merely dictatorship) – one after the other, one more brutally than the other, have demonstrated that human dignity needs a new guarantee which can be found only in a new political principle, in a new law on Earth, whose validity this time must comprehend the whole of humanity while its power must remain strictly limited, rooted in and controlled by newly defined territorial entities. – Hannah Arendt, Summer 1950, Preface to the first edition of the Origins of Totalitarianism



This review is of chapter 5 of Hannah Arendt’s book, Origins of Totalitarianism, which is considered by some to be one of the most influential books of the 20th century. The Origins of Totalitarianism is organized in three parts. Part one, Antisemitism chapters 1-4, Imperialism, chapters 5-9, and Totalitarianism, chapters 10-13. Public interest in this book increased sharply after the election of Donald Trump in 2016.

REVIEW: The Political Emancipation of the Bourgeoisie (chapter 5): Chapter 5 opens with the observation that the 30-year span from 1884 to 1914 marked the height of Western imperialism. The imperialist period had characteristics of the rise of totalitarianism. Arendt observed that it “may be justifiable to consider the whole period a preparatory stage for coming catastrophes” in the form of the coming totalitarianisms under Hitler and Stalin. She argues that imperialism’s central event was the political emancipation of the bourgeoisie, “which up to then had been the first class in history to achieve economic pre-eminence without aspiring to political rule.” Emancipation was necessitated once it became apparent that “the nation-state proved to be unfit to be the framework for further growth of capitalist economy.” Once that realization dawned on the bourgeoisie, the “latent fight between state and society” became an open power struggle. During this 30-year period, neither the bourgeoisie nor the state decisively won. The decisive bourgeoisie win came later:
National institutions resisted throughout the brutality and megalomania of imperialist aspirations, and bourgeois attempts to use the state and its instruments of violence for its own economic purposes were always only half successful. This changed when the German bourgeoisie staked everything on the Hitler movement and aspired to rule with the help of the mob, but then it turned out to be too late. The bourgeoisie succeeded in destroying the nation-state but won a Pyrrhic victory; the mob proved quite capable of taking care of politics itself and liquidated the bourgeoisie along with all other classes and institutions.

In the struggle between traditional politicians and the capitalists who wanted state power behind their ambitions to conquer the world, and if they could the planets, the politicians were largely blindsided by what capitalism and the industrial revolution could do. Arendt describes European statesmen as having lost touch with the reality that trade and economic concerns had already entangled every nation in world politics. “The national principle was leading to provincial ignorance and the battle fought by sanity was lost.” The insanity Arendt refers to is the clash between civil society and the insanity of brutal subjugation of colonized populations in the name of wealth accumulation. The imperialist conquest of foreign lands ignites in the subjugated populations national aspirations that were not there to begin with and therein lies the beginning of the end for imperialist conquests. The existing generation of European politicians thought in terms of existing nations and opposed the idea of imperialist expansion. They misunderstood the raw power that the drive for unlimited wealth can exert.

Arendt asserts that “expansion as a permanent and supreme aim of politics is the central political idea of imperialism.” As a political thought, this was new in human history, which is a very rare event. However, she argues this idea is not a matter of politics. Instead, the imperialist ideal is a matter of business, where business expansion backed by state power is nothing more than an attempt to build a permanent broadening of means of production and markets.

How a competition between fully armed business concerns – empires – could end in anything but victory for one and death for the others is difficult to understand. In other words, competition is no more a principle of politics than expansion, and needs political power just as badly for control and restraint.

Of the European powers, only France tried to build an Empire roughly modeled on the ancient Roman Empire. The failure of Napoleon to unite European nations under the French flag was evidence that conquered lands would develop a national consciousness and rebelliousness, leading to successful rebellion or tyranny by the conquering nation. France tried this out of fear of its powerful neighbors, especially Germany. People living in areas such as Algeria that France conquered were envisioned as French citizens who would come to the mother country’s aid in time of need. She saw conquered people as inexpensive cannon fodder for the next war. Arendt took a dim view of how that played out: “The result of this daring enterprise was a particularly brutal exploitation of overseas possessions for the sake of the nation.”

The British attempt to build a commonwealth did not fare much better. Ireland never accepted the idea. “The Irish example proves how ill fitted the United Kingdom was to build an imperial structure in which many different people could live contentedly together.” Perhaps we see echoes of this today in modern Scotland where a local temptation to stay with the European Union is being toyed with as the UK nears Brexit. The imperialists were basically ruthless, immoral businessmen, not statesmen. In this maybe one can see why the bourgeoisie was not much interested in politics until national resources and populations were beginning to limit the growth of profits and there were no good investment opportunities left in the mother land. Expansion by conquest backed by national power was the only option that might render their massive wealth something more than almost useless.



Hobbes and the rise of private interest: Despite her assertion that imperialism is not politics, but is business, Arendt states that political philosopher Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) in his book Leviathan anticipated the rise of government based on personal interest instead of national interest.
Hobbes’s Leviathan exposed the only political theory according to which the state is based not on some kind of constituting law – whether divine law, the law of nature, or the law of social contract – which determines the rights and wrongs of the individual’s interest with respect to public affairs, but on the individual interests themselves, so that ‘the private interest is the same with the publique’. There is hardly a single bourgeois moral standard that has not been anticipated by the unequaled magnificence of Hobbes’s logic. He gives an almost complete picture, not of Man, but of the bourgeois man, an analysis which in three hundred years has neither been outdated nor excelled. ‘Reason . . . . is nothing but Reckoning; ‘a free Subject, a free Will [are] . . . . words without meaning; that is to say, Absurd.’. . . . if man is actually driven by nothing more than his individual interests, desire for power must be the fundamental passion for man. . . . . Thus membership in any form of community is for Hobbes a temporary and limited affair which essentially does not change the solitary and private character of the individual . . . . or create permanent bonds between him and his fellow men.

Arendt asserts that Hobbes had anticipated by over 300 years the 20th century rise of an anti-traditional bourgeoisie and its self-centered value of endless wealth accumulation as a new political class. Apparently, Hobbes was one of those uncommonly astute observers of human nature who also had a knack for relentlessly applying cold logic to what he saw. Despite Hobbes, Arendt again argues that this is not a matter of politics, but human nature. In her view, the inevitable death of the individual is a central consideration: “Death is the real reason why property and acquisition can never become a true political principle.” At most, all the capitalist could do to fully secure his wealth is destroy it before he dies.

In Hobbes view, nations are tribes always against one another. There is a perpetual war of all against all, because that is the ‘state of nature’ for man. Arendt sees an inevitable end of the quest for expansion: “If the last victorious Commonwealth cannot proceed to ‘annex the planets’, it can only proceed to destroy itself in order to begin anew the never-ending process of power generation.”

Racism: Despite the insight that Arendt sees in Hobbes’ work, she asserts that he missed one factor, namely, modern racism as a rhetorical tool to stir the passions of the mob. Despite the omission, she argues that Hobbes laid the political groundwork for later racism.
The philosophy of Hobbes, it is true, contains nothing of modern race doctrines, which not only stir up the mob, but in their totalitarian form outline very clearly the forms of organization through which humanity could carry the endless process of capital and power accumulation through to its logical end in self-destruction. But Hobbes at least provided political thought with the prerequisite for all race doctrines, that is, the exclusion in principle of the idea of humanity which constitutes the sole regulating idea of international law. . . . . If it should be proved to be true that we are imprisoned in Hobbes’s endless process of power accumulation then the organization of the mob will inevitably take the form of transformation of nations into races, for there is, . . . . no other unifying bond available between individuals who in the very process of power accumulation and expansion are losing all natural connections with their fellow men. Racism may indeed carry out the doom of the Western world, and for that matter, the whole of human civilization. . . . . For no matter what learned scientists may say, politically speaking, not the beginning of humanity but its end, not the origins of people but their decay, not the natural birth of man but his unnatural death.

Arendt describes the mob as composed of the “refuse” of all classes and not the people as a whole. This class was the by-product of bourgeois society and thus not completely separable from it. She describes the mob as “the riff-raff of bohemians, crackpots, gangsters and conspirators.” Later in her book, she asserts that the mob is where totalitarians first find support as they make their run for power and control.

  -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Cognitive science, social science and the anti-bias ideology: Arendt argues in chapter 6 that in human history, only two political ideologies stood the test of time and persuasive attack. The first ideology interprets history as a struggle of economic classes. The second interprets history as a “natural fight of races.” She argues that these two ideas are deeply embedded in modern thinking and perceptions of reality: “The appeal of both to large masses was so strong that they were able to enlist state support and establish themselves as official national doctrines. . . . . . free public opinion has adopted them [class thinking and race thinking] to such an extent that not only intellectuals but great masses of people will no longer accept a presentation of past or present facts that is not in agreement with either of these views.”

From a sociological point of view, Arendt’s description of class and race thinking describes modern social institutions. In his book, Invitation to Sociology, sociologist Peter Berger makes it clear that, for people who inhabit the institution, social institutions shape both perceptions of reality and the thinking people apply to what they think they see.[1] Berger describes the racism institution of the American South as utterly mesmerizing for its adherents. In this regard, Arendt was correct to believe that race thinking constitutes a subtle but powerful mental trap that makes alternative views simply incoherent at best and a pack of lies at worst.

There is no obvious reason to believe that class thinking is any less subtle or powerful. In this reviewer’s experience, Arendt goes a long way to explain both the harsh anti-capitalist mindset of class thinkers, and the basis for fear and social unease among populist movements that are ongoing now in Europe, America, Brazil and elsewhere. Those populist movements are significantly, probably mostly, driven by race thinking. At least, that is what it looks like to this observer, and there is some empirical evidence to support that belief.[2]

Although Arendt could not have access to the mass of knowledge that cognitive and social sciences generated in the decades after she wrote The Origins of Totalitarianism, what she is describing is largely in accord with current scientific knowledge. Her assertion that people usually do not believe facts that contradict world views is spot on. The evidence on that point is not in dispute among experts. Also not disputed is the power of society and social institutions to trap and narrow what minds see and how they think. Some of Arendt’s facts or arguments may now be open to reinterpretation in light of later scholarship, but she nonetheless did see through her experiences to construct a plausible, probably mostly correct assessment of why and how 20th century imperialism developed.

In terms of political ideology, Arendt makes no proposals in chapter 5. The anti-bias ideology with its four highest moral values advocated here does not seem to fit with either class thinking or race thinking. The ideology is silent on class and race and instead looks to politics where interests compete on the more or less objective merits. Class thinkers, mainly socialists and communists, have criticized the anti-bias ideology because of its lack of explicit consideration for class.

All of this raises a question about whether it is possible for a ‘non-biological’ or race-neutral, and class-neutral political ideology can ever gain much, or any, significant level of public acceptance. It is likely impossible unless a social institution can be built around the concept. Human biology and social thinking and behavior cannot be ignored, nor will they change or go away any time soon. Politics as usual, with all of its lies, deceit and unwarranted emotional manipulation, including irrational appeal to racism, also is not going to go away either. Short of overt violence, all of the dark arts that politicians, partisans, billionaires and blowhards can bring to bear are legal and constitutionally protected. From a cognitive and social science point of view, those dark arts arguably have built social institutions, or something close to it, e.g., the current American vision of conservatism, liberalism, capitalism, socialism and so on.

One last thought. Is the anti-bias ideology a new thought in politics? Arendt correctly points out that there is not much left that is new. What is new is the mass of science knowledge that can be brought to bear. But that begs the question of whether people even want to be at least somewhat less biased and more rational about politics. Politics as it is now is easy and enjoyable because it is usually quite self-affirming. Facing unvarnished reality and applying cold logic can lead to unpleasant, self-denigrating or confusing conclusions. That seems to argue for a need to build a social institution if anti-bias is to ever have any chance of exerting political and social influence.

Footnote:
1. “Society not only controls our movements, but shapes our identity, our thought, and our emotions.” Social institutions are therefore, to a significant extent, “structures of our own consciousness. Sociologists speak of ‘ideology’ in discussing views that serve to rationalize the vested interests of some group. Very frequently, such views systematically distort social reality in much the same way that an individual may neurotically deny, deform or reinterpret aspects of his life that are inconvenient to him. . . . . the ideas by which men explain their actions are unmasked as self-deception, sales talk, the kind of ‘sincerity’ that David Riesman has aptly described as the state of mind of a man who habitually believes his own propaganda.”

2. “Support for Donald J. Trump in the 2016 election was widely attributed to citizens who were “left behind” economically. These claims were based on the strong cross-sectional relationship between Trump support and lacking a college education. Using a representative panel from 2012 to 2016, I find that change in financial wellbeing had little impact on candidate preference. Instead, changing preferences were related to changes in the party’s positions on issues related to American global dominance and the rise of a majority–minority America: issues that threaten white Americans’ sense of dominant group status.”

This reviewer interprets concern over “American global dominance” as possibly including a racial component. The rise of China as a challenger to American dominance arguably includes a perceived Chinese race for at least some race-thinking Americans is a plausible source of unease, conscious or not.

Whether we like it or not, or deny it or not, humans are human. We cannot escape our biological and social heritage.

B&B orig: 1/6/19